Reflections on the ethical debate surrounding non-invasive prenatal genetic diagnosis
Women considering invasive testing must weigh the risk of losing a healthy fetus against the risk of bringing a fetus affected by a genetic condition to term. By eliminating the risk of miscarriage, this new technology promises tremendous benefits. It is a long-awaited achievement with the potential to revolutionise prenatal care.
At the same time, this technology is igniting an ethical debate regarding both its medical and non-medical uses. In the non-medical context, there are concerns that testing will lead society down a dangerous eugenic slippery slope where parents choose early abortions for frivolous reasons and select babies for desired traits.
A recent publication (3) confirming the test's reliability for determining the fetus' sex as early as seven weeks raised concerns about its non-medical use together with early sex-selective abortion in societies with a strong cultural preference for males.
Regulating early abortion isn't the appropriate way to address these ethical and social concerns. First-trimester abortion is - and should remain - a woman's prerogative. Her freedom to choose it should not be called into question.
Rather, these concerns should be seen as an opportunity to promote a social debate emphasising values like human dignity, equality and solidarity in our reproductive decision-making. Prospective parents should be encouraged to consider why they're choosing to terminate an otherwise wanted pregnancy and the implications of their choices for themselves, for their potential future child, and for society.
The future medical use of this new technology has also raised concerns. A risk-free maternal blood test may become accessible enough to become an inherent part of prenatal care.
Current prenatal care involves a two-step approach. Women are offered non-invasive screening using a maternal blood test combined with ultrasound. If the results raise concerns, the screening is followed by counselling about and consent for invasive diagnostic testing.
This two-step approach provides women with some built-in protection from exposure to unwanted diagnostic information. Counselling ensures women fully understand the risks of choosing invasive testing and the implications of the information they will obtain by choosing to take this risk.
Once the need for screening is eliminated, we can assume clinical practice will adopt a one-step approach in which a diagnostic blood test is as routine as ultrasound is today. But diagnostic testing without appropriate counselling and consent threatens pregnant women's autonomy to make informed decisions about what they wish to know about the fetus they are carrying (4).
Even within today's two-step approach, consent procedures for prenatal genetic screening are not appropriate and need enhancing (5). The transition to a one-step approach is likely to exacerbate this problem, particularly in light of the growing tendency toward the 'medicalisation' of pregnancy and pressures created by a medical system that favours testing.
These concerns about non-invasive testing are legitimate and deserve close examination. However, considering its tremendous benefits, they do not justify delaying its integration into clinical practice.
Rather, this is an important opportunity for clinicians, bioethicists and regulators to consider in advance possible risks and identify counselling and consent mechanisms to protect and promote autonomous decision-making.