Subscribe to the BioNews newsletter for free

Login
Advanced Search

Search for
BioNews


Print Page Follow BioNews on Twitter BioNews RSS feed

Like the Progress Educational Trust on Facebook








Consent for embryo creation and storage: time for a change in the law?

17 May 2010

By Dr Anna Smajdor

Lecturer in Ethics at the University of East Anglia

Appeared in BioNews 558
When Natallie Evans lost her case to prevent the destruction of her embryos in 2007, many people were moved by her plight. The letter of the law had been followed, but with tragic consequences for her. A recently-published paper by Sozou, Hartshorne and Sheldon argues for a new approach to consent in this context: both parents would consent to the initial creation and storage of the embryos, but one parent could subsequently relinquish their 'ownership', leaving the other to choose how, when and whether to use the embryos.

So how - if at all - would this have changed things for Natallie Evans? If her partner had opted to relinquish control to her, she could have implanted her embryos. But why would he choose to do so? If a man has misgivings about the idea of parenthood at this stage, his doubts will not be resolved by relinquishing his right to be involved in all future decisions relating to the embryos.

But perhaps this option might at least flush the reluctant partners out of the woodwork. If Mr Johnston had been offered the chance to cede control of the embryos to Ms Evans, and had refused, she might have become aware much earlier of the fact that he was not fully committed. She could then have considered saving some of her eggs to be fertilised with donor sperm so that if Mr Johnston did withdraw his consent, she would still have some chance of having a child with her own eggs.

However, there are a number of difficulties here. Firstly, if there are very few eggs available it may not be feasible to hedge one's bets in this way. Secondly, one might fail to recognise the 'warning' implied by the spouse or partner's refusal to cede control of the embryos. Thirdly, donor gametes are in short supply, so there may be complications if a delay is required, since eggs cannot easily be frozen.

The fourth - and perhaps most significant - flaw in this proposal is the question of whether such an agreement could really be treated as binding. Choosing to become a parent is a momentous and significant event that affects some of the most deeply-held values that people can have. Sozou, Hartshorne and Sheldon suggest that we shouldn't attempt to protect individuals by preventing them from signing away these choices, as this would be unduly paternalistic. But even if we agree that paternalism is not warranted, problems will arise if individuals change their minds.

In such cases, the enforcement of the law might seem just as problematic as it was for Natallie Evans. Relinquishment of embryos at an early stage might be bitterly regretted later on. Circumstances may change in ways that were not foreseen at the outset. A man who has allowed embryos to be created with his sperm five years ago may feel very differently about the prospect of their being used, for example after he has married someone else and had children with her. A man who relinquishes his rights over embryos created with his sperm could argue compellingly that he was not - and could not reasonably have been - aware of how he would feel when the time came. This might undermine the ethical if not the legal validity of consent given in such circumstances.

One can foresee, if this were made law, that some men might try to rescind their agreement, or dispute the terms under which the original contract were drawn up. This in turn would place more pressure on the consent process itself, and on the staff who usher patients through this process. The authors suggest that clinics already provide good consent procedures for patients, so the adoption of this new legislation would only add a small amount of extra work.

However, anecdotal evidence suggests otherwise. Patients are often rushed through the consent process by staff who are busy and unable to spell out every possibility to patients. Patients are often bewildered, intimidated, or simply distracted. (In Ms Evans' case, consent forms were being signed just after she had been told of her cancer diagnosis). In this less than perfect world, there is ample scope for sloppy or inadequate briefing, which may undermine the validity of consent.

Such complaints might have limited legal strength, but the emotive appeal could be just as powerful as that of Natallie Evans' situation. What's more, the man in this situation suffers on two fronts. Not only are his reproductive wishes thwarted, he is also potentially faced with a legal obligation to support the offspring whose creation he opposes. The justice of enforcing a long term financial burden on the basis of an agreement that may have been made years before, and in circumstances which have altogether altered, seems highly dubious.

The authors do not explicitly discuss this issue; it may be that they assume financial responsibility would also be signed away. But without specifically assuring this, their proposed changes to the consent arrangements are problematic.

Ms Evans received a great deal of public sympathy, hence the view that the law should change. But the change proposed by Sozou, Hartshorne and Sheldon simply creates new potential objects of sympathy: the men who sign away their rights and may later regret doing so. It is not obvious why this is any better than the original situation. Given the issue about financial maintenance, it could be argued that it is worse. The existing law in this area is not perfect, but the suggested changes look distinctly unpromising, unless accompanied by a much more sweeping overhaul of the law in this area.

A woman who wishes her partner to relinquish his legal rights over jointly-created embryos would perhaps be better off seeking a bona fide sperm donor, whose rights and responsibilities are clearly set out in law. And a man who would commit himself in advance to an agreement of the kind set out in this proposal would have to be extraordinarily virtuous... or perhaps simply foolish.

 

SOURCES & REFERENCES

RELATED ARTICLES FROM THE BIONEWS ARCHIVE

30 September 2013 - by Antony Blackburn-Starza 
A woman in the USA is embroiled in a legal battle with her former partner over the use of cryopreserved embryos... [Read More]
19 March 2012 - by Jessica Ware 
A US scheme that promotes the 'adoption' of embryos produced during IVF but not implanted is likely to have its government funding withdrawn in the next financial year... [Read More]
28 November 2011 - by Professor Eric Blyth and Dr Lucy Frith 
In the US the relinquishment of embryos for family building is the subject of intense ideological debate. This has occurred not least because of the competing discourses of models of 'embryo donation' and 'embryo adoption'... [Read More]
06 June 2011 - by Nisha Satkunarajah 
A man who froze his sperm at a fertility clinic over ten years ago has spoken of his distress after finding out his ex-wife had tricked the clinic into using the sperm, resulting in the birth of two children. He was then ordered by a court to pay 100,000 towards their upbringing... [Read More]
18 October 2010 - by Owen Clark 
A healthy baby has been born from an embryo frozen for almost 20 years – the oldest frozen embryo to result in a live birth... [Read More]

10 April 2007 - by Dr Jess Buxton 
The UK woman fighting to use stored frozen embryos against the wishes of her former partner has lost her final appeal. Natallie Evans underwent IVF with Howard Johnston in 2001, before Ms Evans had treatment for ovarian cancer that left her infertile. Mr Johnston later withdrew... [Read More]
07 March 2006 - by BioNews 
The European Court of Human Rights (ECHR) has issued its judgment in the case of Evans v the United Kingdom. Natallie Evans, a British woman seeking the right to be able to use her own frozen IVF embryos, asked the court last September to rule whether UK law preventing her... [Read More]

HAVE YOUR SAY
Be the first to have your say.

You need to or  to add comments.

By posting a comment you agree to abide by the BioNews terms and conditions

 


 

- click here to enquire about using this story.

Printer Friendly Page

Published by the Progress Educational Trust
Advertise your products and services HERE - click for further details

Become a Friend of PET HERE and give the Progress Educational Trust a regular donation

Good Fundraising Code

Find out more about the Progress Educational Trust by downloading our brochure HERE